Sophist 254
Sophist 258d-259b

Visitor: We've pushed our investigation ahead and shown him something even beyond what he prohibited us from even thinking about.
Tht.: In what way?
V.: Because he says, remember,
    Never shall it force itself on us, that that which is not may be;
    Keep your thought far away from this path of searching.

Tht. That's what he says.
V. But we've not only shown that those which are not are. We've also caused what turns out to be the form of that which is not to appear. Since we showed that the nature of the different is, chopped up among all beings in relation to each other, we dared to say that that which is not really is just this, namely, each part of the nature of the different that's set over against that which is.
Tht.: And what we've said seem to me completely and totally true.
V. Nobody can say that this that which is not, which we've made to appear and now dare to say is, is the contrary of that which is. We've said good-bye long ago to any contrary of that which is, and to whether it is or not, and also to whether or not an account can be given of it. With regard to that which is not, which we've said is, let someone refute us and persuade us that we've made a mistake--or else , so long as he can't do that, he should say just what we say. He has to say that the kinds blend with each other, that that which is and the different pervade all of them and each other, that the different shares in that which is and so, because of that sharing, is. But he won't say that it is that which it shares in, but that it is different from it, and necessarily, because it  is different from that which is, it clearly can be what is not. On the other hand, that which is has a share in the different, so, being different from all of the others, it is not each of them and it is not all of the others except itself. So that which is indisputably is not millions of things, and all of the others together, and also each of them, are in many ways and also are not in many ways.
Tht. True.
V. And if anyone doesn't believe these contrarieties, he has to think about them himself and say something better than what we've said. But if he thinks he's recognized a problem in it and enjoys dragging the argument back and forth, then he's been carried away by something that's not worth much of anyone's attention--to go by what we've just been saying, anyway. A thing like that isn't clever or hard to discover, but the other thing is both difficult and at the same time beautiful.
Tht. What other thing?
C. The thing we said earlier. That is, we should leave pointless things like this alone. Instead, we should be able to follow what a person says and scrutinize it step by step. When he says that what's different is the same in a certain way or that what's the same is different in a certain way, we should understand just what way he means, and the precise respect in which he's saying that the thing is the same or different. But when someone makes that which is the same appear different in just any old way, or vice versa, or when he makes what's large appear small or something that's similar appear dissimilar--well, if someone enjoys constantly trotting out contraries like that in discussion, that's not true refutation. It's only the obvious new-born-brain-child of someone who just came into contact with those which are.
Tht. Definitely.
...